막스 슈티르너 (Korean Wikipedia)

Analysis of information sources in references of the Wikipedia article "막스 슈티르너" in Korean language version.

refsWebsite
Global rank Korean rank
1st place
1st place
9,546th place
1,828th place
low place
low place
5,270th place
6,087th place
179th place
146th place
low place
low place
3rd place
9th place
low place
low place
low place
low place
26th place
70th place
5th place
11th place
low place
low place
30th place
129th place
1,089th place
low place
8,043rd place
6,166th place
low place
low place
1,252nd place
low place

books.google.com

calpress.org

i-studies.com

jstor.org

libcom.org

libertyfund.org

oll.libertyfund.org

  • "Only the influence of the German philosopher of egoism, Max Stirner (né Johann Kaspar Schmidt, 1806–1856), as expressed through The Ego and His Own (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum) compared with that of Proudhon. In adopting Stirnerite egoism (1886), Tucker rejected natural rights which had long been considered the foundation of libertarianism. This rejection galvanized the movement into fierce debates, with the natural rights proponents accusing the egoists of destroying libertarianism itself. So bitter was the conflict that a number of natural rights proponents withdrew from the pages of Liberty in protest even though they had hitherto been among its frequent contributors. Thereafter, Liberty championed egoism although its general content did not change significantly."Wendy Mcelroy. "Benjamin Tucker, Individualism, & Liberty: Not the Daughter but the Mother of Order" Archived 2011년 5월 24일 - 웨이백 머신

literaturwissenschaft.de

  • Bernd A. Laska. Otto Gross zwischen Max Stirner und Wilhelm Reich 보관됨 4 3월 2016 - 웨이백 머신, In: Raimund Dehmlow and Gottfried Heuer, eds.: 3. Internationaler Otto-Gross-Kongress, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, München. Marburg, 2003, pp. 125–162, ISBN 3-936134-06-5 LiteraturWissenschaft.de .

lsr-projekt.de

  • Bernd A. Laska. Otto Gross zwischen Max Stirner und Wilhelm Reich 보관됨 4 3월 2016 - 웨이백 머신, In: Raimund Dehmlow and Gottfried Heuer, eds.: 3. Internationaler Otto-Gross-Kongress, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, München. Marburg, 2003, pp. 125–162, ISBN 3-936134-06-5 LiteraturWissenschaft.de .
  • See Bernd A. Laska: Nietzsche's initial crisis. In: Germanic Notes and Reviews, vol. 33, n. 2, fall/Herbst 2002, pp. 109–133
  • Max Stirner, a durable dissident – in a nutshell
  • See Bernd A. Laska: Ein dauerhafter Dissident. Nürnberg: LSR-Verlag 1996 (online)
  • See Bernd A. Laska: Katechon und Anarch. Nürnberg: LSR-Verlag 1997 (online)
  • Bernd A. Laska: Nietzsche's initial crisis. In: Germanic Notes and Reviews, vol. 33, n. 2, fall/Herbst 2002, pp. 109–133

nonserviam.com

raforum.info

stanford.edu

plato.stanford.edu

telegraph.co.uk

theanarchistlibrary.org

  • Raoul Vaneigem. The Revolution of Everyday Life 보관됨 16 5월 2020 - 웨이백 머신.
  • https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/mikhail-bakunin-the-reaction-in-germany
  • https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/max-stirner-stirner-s-critics
  • https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/max-stirner-the-ego-and-his-own The craving for a particular freedom always includes the purpose of a new dominion, as it was with the Revolution, which indeed “could give its defenders the uplifting feeling that they were fighting for freedom,” but in truth only because they were after a particular freedom, therefore a new dominion, the “dominion of the law.” Freedom you all want, you want freedom. Why then do you haggle over a more or less? Freedom can only be the whole of freedom; a piece of freedom is not freedom. You despair of the possibility of obtaining the whole of freedom, freedom from everything — yes, you consider it insanity even to wish this? — Well, then leave off chasing after the phantom, and spend your pains on something better than the — unattainable.
  • The commoner is what he is through the protection of the State, through the State’s grace. He would necessarily be afraid of losing everything if the State’s power were broken. But how is it with him who has nothing to lose, how with the proletarian? As he has nothing to lose, he does not need the protection of the State for his “nothing.” He may gain, on the contrary, if that protection of the State is withdrawn from the protégé. Therefore the non-possessor will regard the State as a power protecting the possessor, which privileges the latter, but does nothing for him, the non-possessor, but to — suck his blood. The State is a — commoners’ State, is the estate of the commonalty. It protects man not according to his labor, but according to his tractableness (“loyalty”) — to wit, according to whether the rights entrusted to him by the State are enjoyed and managed in accordance with the will, i. e., laws, of the State. Under the regime of the commonalty the laborers always fall into the hands of the possessors, of those who have at their disposal some bit of the State domains (and everything possessible in State domain, belongs to the State, and is only a fief of the individual), especially money and land; of the capitalists, therefore. The laborer cannot realize on his labor to the extent of the value that it has for the consumer. “Labor is badly paid!” The capitalist has the greatest profit from it. — Well paid, and more than well paid, are only the labors of those who heighten the splendor and dominion of the State, the labors of high State servants. The State pays well that its “good citizens,” the possessors, may be able to pay badly without danger; it secures to itself by good payment its servants, out of whom it forms a protecting power, a “police” (to the police belong soldiers, officials of all kinds, e.g. those of justice, education, etc. — in short, the whole “machinery of the State”) for the “good citizens,” and the “good citizens” gladly pay high tax-rates to it in order to pay so much lower rates to their laborers. But the class of laborers, because unprotected in what they essentially are (for they do not enjoy the protection of the State as laborers, but as its subjects they have a share in the enjoyment of the police, a so-called protection of the law), remains a power hostile to this State, this State of possessors, this “citizen kingship.” Its principle, labor, is not recognized as to its value; it is exploited,[ausgebeutet] a spoil [Kriegsbeute] of the possessors, the enemy. The laborers have the most enormous power in their hands, and, if they once became thoroughly conscious of it and used it, nothing would withstand them; they would only have to stop labor, regard the product of labor as theirs, and enjoy it. This is the sense of the labor disturbances which show themselves here and there. The State rests on the — slavery of labor. If labor becomes free. the State is lost. The Ego and its Own
  • https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/abissonichilista-the-unique-one-meets-the-overhuman
  • https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/max-stirner-stirner-s-critics If Stirner had said: You are more than a living essence or animal, this would mean, you are still an animal, but animality does not exhaust what you are......

unirioja.es

dialnet.unirioja.es

web.archive.org

  • Bernd A. Laska. Otto Gross zwischen Max Stirner und Wilhelm Reich 보관됨 4 3월 2016 - 웨이백 머신, In: Raimund Dehmlow and Gottfried Heuer, eds.: 3. Internationaler Otto-Gross-Kongress, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, München. Marburg, 2003, pp. 125–162, ISBN 3-936134-06-5 LiteraturWissenschaft.de .
  • Raoul Vaneigem. The Revolution of Everyday Life 보관됨 16 5월 2020 - 웨이백 머신.
  • Wolfi Landstreicher. The Unique and Its Property 보관됨 25 6월 2020 - 웨이백 머신
  • Iwan Bloch. Der Marquis de Sade und seine Zeit 보관됨 13 4월 2021 - 웨이백 머신
  • Jason McQuinn. Clarifying the Unique and Its Self-Creation: An introduction to “Stirner’s Critics” and “The Philosophical Reactionaries” 보관됨 9 11월 2020(날짜 불일치) - 웨이백 머신
  • John Henry Mackay: Max Stirner – Sein Leben und sein Werk Archived 2016년 11월 9일 - 웨이백 머신 p. 28
  • “보관된 사본”. 2018년 2월 5일에 원본 문서에서 보존된 문서. 2018년 1월 6일에 확인함. 
  • 울피 랜드스트라이커(Wolfi Landstreicher)의 2017년 번역본 Archived 2018년 2월 5일 - 웨이백 머신에서는 phantasm으로 번역되었다.
  • Nyberg, Svein Olav. “The union of egoists” (PDF). 《Non Serviam》 (Oslo, Norway: Svein Olav Nyberg) 1: 13–14. OCLC 47758413. 2010년 12월 7일에 원본 문서 (PDF)에서 보존된 문서. 2012년 9월 1일에 확인함. 
  • “보관된 사본”. 2018년 2월 5일에 원본 문서에서 보존된 문서. 2018년 1월 6일에 확인함. 
  • Wilson, A N (2004년 11월 1일). “World of books”. 《The Daily Telegraph》 (London). 2010년 5월 12일에 확인함. [깨진 링크(과거 내용 찾기)]
  • "Only the influence of the German philosopher of egoism, Max Stirner (né Johann Kaspar Schmidt, 1806–1856), as expressed through The Ego and His Own (Der Einzige und sein Eigentum) compared with that of Proudhon. In adopting Stirnerite egoism (1886), Tucker rejected natural rights which had long been considered the foundation of libertarianism. This rejection galvanized the movement into fierce debates, with the natural rights proponents accusing the egoists of destroying libertarianism itself. So bitter was the conflict that a number of natural rights proponents withdrew from the pages of Liberty in protest even though they had hitherto been among its frequent contributors. Thereafter, Liberty championed egoism although its general content did not change significantly."Wendy Mcelroy. "Benjamin Tucker, Individualism, & Liberty: Not the Daughter but the Mother of Order" Archived 2011년 5월 24일 - 웨이백 머신
  • “BONANNO, Alfredo Maria”. 2009년 7월 10일에 원본 문서에서 보존된 문서. 2009년 7월 10일에 확인함. 

worldcat.org

zeno.org